The Undecidability of Post's Correspondence Problem
Applications of Post's Correspondence Problem
The Post's Correspondence Problem, or PCP for short, consists of the following domain and question.
with infinitely many cards in each pile, can one draw a sequence of n 1
cards
from these piles, so that the string xi1
xin formed on the top of the cards will
equal the string yi1
yin formed on the bottom?
The tuple (i1, i2, i3, i4, i5, i6) = (1, 3, 2, 4, 4, 3) is a witness for a positive solution
because x1x3x2x4x4x3 = y1y3y2y4y4y3 = 01111001011111. The positive solution has
also the witnesses (1, 3, 2, 4, 4, 3, 1, 3, 2, 4, 4, 3), (1, 3, 2, 4, 4,3,1,3,2,4,4,3,1,3,2, 4, 4, 3),
etc. On the other hand, the PCP has the solution no for <(0, 10), (01, 1)>.
The Undecidability of Post's Correspondence Problem
Post's correspondence problem is very useful for showing the undecidability of many other problems by means of reducibility. Its undecidability follows from its capacity for simulating the computations of Turing machines, as exhibited indirectly in the following proof through derivations in Type 0 grammars.
Theorem 4.7.1 The PCP is an undecidable problem.
Proof By Corollary 4.6.1 the membership problem is undecidable for Type 0 grammars. Thus, it is sufficient to show how from each instance (G, w) of the membership problem for Type 0 grammars, an instance I can be constructed, such that the PCP has a positive solution at I if and only if w is in L(G).
For the purpose of the proof consider any Type 0 grammar G = <N, , P, S> and
any string w in
*. With no loss of generality assume that #, ˘, and $ are new symbols not
in N
. Then let the corresponding instance I = <(x1, y1), . . . , (xk, yk)> of PCP be of
the following form.
PCP has a positive solution at I if and only if I can trace a derivation that starts at S and ends at w.
For each derivation in G of the form S
1
m
w, the instance I has a
witness (i1, . . . , in) of a positive solution such that either
or
depending on whether m is even or odd, respectively.
On the other hand, each witness (i1, . . . , in) of a positive solution for PCP at I
has a smallest integer t 1 such that xi1
xit = yi1
yit. In such a case,
xi1
xit = yi1
yit = ˘S
#
2
#
4
m
for some derivation
S
*
1
*
2
*
*
m
* w.
The instance I consists of pairs of the following form
The other pairs are used to force the tracing to go from each given sentential form to
a sentential form
', such that
*
'. The tracing is possible because each of the pairs
(xi, yi) is defined so that yi provides a "window" into
, whereas xi provides an
appropriate replacement for yi in
'.
The pairs of the form (X, ) and (
, X) in (c) are used for copying substrings
from
to
'. The pairs of the form (
,
) and (
,
),
, in (d) are used for
replacing substrings
in
by substrings
in
'. The pairs of the form (X,
) and
(
, X
) in (e) are used for replacing substrings
in
by the empty string
in
'.
The window is provided because for each 1 i1, . . . , ij
k, the strings
x = xi1
xij and y = yi1
yij satisfy the following properties.
Example 4.7.2
If G is a grammar whose set of production rules is {S aSaSaS, aS
},
then the instance of the PCP that corresponds to (G,
) as determined by the
proof of Theorem 4.7.1, is <(˘S
, ˘), (
, S), (aSaSaS,
), (
, #aS),
(#,
), (
, aaS), (a,
), (
, SaS), (S,
), (#,
), (
, #), (a,
), (
, a), (S,
),
(
, S), ($,
$)>.
The instance has a positive solution with a witness that corresponds to the arrangement in Figure 4.7.1.
![]()
|
Applications of Post's Correspondence Problem
The following corollary exhibits how Post's correspondence problem can be used to show the undecidability of some other problems by means of reducibility.
Corollary 4.7.1 The equivalence problem is undecidable for finite-state transducers.
Proof
Consider any instance <(x1, y1), . . . , (xk, yk)> of PCP. Let be the minimal alphabet
such that x1, . . . , xk, y1, . . . , yk are all in
*. With no loss of generality assume that
= {1, . . . , k} is an alphabet.
Let M1 = <Q1, ,
,
1, q0, F1> be a finite-state transducer that computes the
relation
* ×
*, that is, a finite-state transducer that accepts all inputs over
, and on
each such input can output any string over
.
Let M2 = <Q2, ,
,
2, q0, F2> be a finite-state transducer that on input i1
in
outputs some w such that either w
xi1
xin or w
yi1
yin. Thus, M2 on input
i1
in can output any string in
* if xi1
xin
yi1
yin. On the other hand, if
xi1
xin = yi1
yin, then M2 on such an input i1
in can output any string in
*,
except for xi1
xin.
It follows that M1 is equivalent to M2 if and only if the PCP has a negative answer at
the given instance <(x1, y1), . . . , (xk, yk)>.
Example 4.7.3
Consider the instance <(x1, y1), (x2, y2)> = <(0, 10), (01, 1)> of PCP. Using the
terminology in the proof of Corollary 4.7.1, = {0, 1} and
= {1, 2}. The finite-state
transducer M1 can be as in Figure 4.7.2(a),
![]()
|
M2 on a given input i1
in nondeterministically chooses between its components
Mx and My. In Mx it outputs a prefix of xi1
xin, and in My it outputs a
prefix of yi1
yin. Then M2 nondeterministically switches to M>, M<, or
M
.
M2 switches from Mx to M> to obtain an output that has xi1
xin as a proper
prefix. M2 switches from Mx to M< to obtain an output that is proper prefix of
xi1
xin. M2 switches from Mx to M
to obtain an output that differs from xi1
xin
within the first |xi1
xin| symbols.
M2 switches from My to M>, M<, M for similar reasons, respectively.
The following corollary has a proof similar to that given for the previous one.
Corollary 4.7.2 The equivalence problem is undecidable for pushdown automata.
Proof
Consider any instance <(x1, y1), . . . , (xk, yk)> of PCP. Let 1 be the minimal alphabet
such that x1, . . . , xk, y1, . . . , yk are all in
1*. With no loss of generality assume that
2 = {1, . . . , k} is an alphabet, that
1 and
2 are mutually disjoint, and that Z0 is a new
symbol not in
1.
Let M1 = <Q1, 1
2,
1
Z0,
1, q0, Z0, F1> be a pushdown automaton
that accepts all the strings in (
1
2)*. (In fact, M1 can also be a finite-state
automaton.)
Let M2 = <Q2, 1
2,
1
Z0,
2, q0, Z0, F2> be a pushdown automaton that
accepts an input w if and only if it is of the form in
i1u, for some i1
in in
1* and
some u in
2*, such that either u
xi1
xin or u
yi1
yin.
It follows that M1 and M2 are equivalent if and only if the PCP has a negative answer
at the given instance.
The pushdown automaton M2 in the proof of Corollary 4.7.2 can be constructed to halt on a given input if and only if it accepts the input. The constructed pushdown automaton halts on all inputs if and only if the PCP has a negative solution at the given instance. Hence, the following corollary is also implied from the undecidability of PCP.
Corollary 4.7.3 The uniform halting problem is undecidable for pushdown automata.
PCP is a partially decidable problem because given an instance <(x1, y1), . . . , (xk, yk)> of the problem one can search exhaustively for a witness of a positive solution, for example, in {1, . . . , k}* in canonical order. With such an algorithm a witness will eventually be found if the instance has a positive solution. Alternatively, if the instance has a negative solution, then the search will never terminate.